The objective here is to find a set of argument forms that are consistently valid. We can show that there are 256 different forms for Categorical Syllogisms, and we can show further that only 15 of those forms are valid arguments (!) That leaves 241 non-valid forms of Categorical Syllogisms. Is there any wonder that there are so many false arguments?
The fun part is that the 15 valid forms of Categorical Syllogisms have been given names. For example, one need not say to a logician any more than “Barbara”, and the logician will immediately know the exact form. I think that is a hoot, and it reminds me of the old joke about the comedian’s convention, where one comedian yells out, “number 47”, and the whole audience laughs…
In order to get to that point we have some things to understand first. Here is a map of where we are headed in this lesson:
1. Standard Form for Categorical Syllogisms.We will need to define some things as we go along.
2. The Concept of “Distribution”.
3. Affirmation / Negation.
4. Contraries and Contradictories.
5. Rules and Fallacies.
6. Moods and Figures.
7. A List of the Valid Categorical Syllogisms (of Standard Form)
1. Standard Form for Categorical Syllogisms
The Structure of Categorical Propositions has a standard form. The form consists of this:
[subject] [some form of the verb “to be”] [ predicate]Example:
[The king of France] [ is ] [bald].This proposition is in a valid form, but is false: France has no king.
2. The Concept of Distribution
Distribution is defined as how much of the population of a set is covered by the proposition. If an element of the proposition refers to an entire population then it is said to be distributed (or “universal”); otherwise it is not distributed (also called “particular”).
Examples:
The modifier, “some”, does not cover the entire population and is thus not distributed.
The modifiers, “all” and “none”, refer to the entire population of the set, and are called distributed.
[All of P] [ is ] [some of Q]: Here P is distributed, and Q is not distributed.3. Affirmation and Negation
Now, recalling the types of propositions, we can further refine them:
A. All Q is P;4. Contraries and ContradictoriesThis means that all of the Q category is a subset of the P category.E. No Q is P;
Q is distributed; P is not distributed.
Q is universal: P is particular.
The statement is affirmative.Q is completely outside and independent of the p category.I. Some Q is P;
Q is distributed; P is distributed.
Both Q and P are universal.
The statement is negativePart of the Q category is inside the P category.
Q is not distributed; P is not distributed.
Q and P are both particular.
The statement is affirmative.
O. Some Q is not P;Part of the Q category is outside of the P category.
Q is not distributed; P is distributed.
Q is particular; P is universal.
The statement is negative.
The relationship between the four types, A, E, I, O, is a square which demonstrates the contrary relationships, the contradictory relationships, and the sub-relationships:
[From Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy]
Here is a table for displaying the same information:
For example, when A is true, its contrary, E is false. When A is true, its contradictory, O is false.
5. Rules and Fallacies
There are some rules for Categorical Syllogisms, and there are associated fallacy names for their false usage:
Rule 1:6. Moods and Figures
Don’t use four terms;
Associated Fallacy: four term fallacy.
Rule 2:
Distribute the middle term for one or more of the premises:
Associated Fallacy: undistributed middle fallacy.
Rule 3:
A distributed term in the conclusion must also be distributed in the premises.
Associated Fallacy: undistributed middle fallacy.
Rule 4:
Do not use two negative premises.
Associated Fallacy: exclusive premise fallacy.
Rule 5:
If one of the premises is negative, then the conclusion is negative as well.
Associated Fallacy: false affirmative from a single negative premise fallacy.
Rule 6.
No particular conclusion is derived from two universal premises.
Associated Fallacy: existential fallacy.
Here we come to an interesting part.
The structure of syllogism is called the “mood”. For example, the mood of a syllogism might be AOE, meaning that premise 1 is of the form A; premise 2 is of the form O; the conclusion is of the form E.
And the syllogism also has a “figure”, which describes the shape with respect to the middle term, M. (S= subject of the conclusion, aka “minor term”; P=predicate of the conclusion, aka “major term”):
Figure 1:Now we are finally able to fully define some arguments merely by referring to some codes. For example, AAA-1 means that the argument is formed of three “all Q are P “ types of statements, in the form of Figure 1.P1: M – PFigure 2:
P2: S – M
C: S – P
(The middle term is the subject in P1; the predicate in P2).P1: P – MFigure 3:
P2: S – M
C: S – PP1: M – PFigure 4:
P2: M – S
C: S – PP1: P – M
P2: M – S
C: S – P
So now we can list the 15 valid arguments and even categorize them with respect to their figures:
7. List of Valid Syllogisms of Standard Form, Categorized by Figure:
Figure 1 Valid Syllogisms:
1. AAA-1 BarbaraFigure 2 Valid Syllogisms
2. EAE-1 Celarent
3. AII-1 Darii
4. EIO-1 Ferio
5. AEE-2 CamestresFigure 3 Valid Syllogisms
6. EAE-2 Cesare
7. AOO-2 Baroko
8. EIO-2 Festino
9. AII-3 DatisiFigure 4 Valid Syllogisms
10. IAI-3 Disamis
11. EIO-3 Ferison
12. OAO-3 Bokardo
13. AEE-4 CamenesOf these, only EIO is valid in all Figures, 1 through 4.
14. IAI-4 Dimaris
15. EIO-4 Fresison
The validity of these arguments has been determined by examining all 256 arguments for violation of the Rules which are listed above. Feel free to repeat that exercise if you wish. (Note 2)
In the next lesson we will investigate the translation of language-based arguments into the coded syllogistic form, so that we can more easily determine the validity of such everyday language arguments.
Notes:
(1) Much of this material was developed with the help of Copi & Cohen, Introduction to Logic, 2005, as well as other sources by Tarski, Frege, Kelley, Tomassi, etc.
(2) I did not do that. Some things are faith-based.
9 comments:
Have you heard of the star test for validity?
Put an asterisk after all distributed terms in the premises, and after all non-distributed terms in the conclusion.
The syllogism is valid if all general terms are starred once and only once, and there is exactly one starred term on the right.
Example:
All A* is B
No B* is C*
Therefore, no A is C
Every general term is starred only once, and there is only one starred term to the right.
I find it a lot easier than remembering all those rules.
I'm not certain what you mean by "general term" and "to the right".
Is a general term referring to an entire premise, or to a subject or predicate?
And to the right of ... what? Perhaps to the right of the "therefore"? Or maybe to the right of the "to be", which would be the predicate of each?
Wait I think I see. General term = either subject or predicate; to the right = to the right of the "to be".
OK. I understand what you are saying, I'd have to run through the 15 to see if it works... What is the source for this trick? Pretty neat if it works (and I presume that it does).
Oh, and it would need to be falsified for the other 241 forms...
Sorry. This is from Harry Gensler. His method is to use a capital letter for general/universal terms (humans, things that are solid, etc) and a lowercase letter for terms that pick out a specific individual (George Bush, the smartest person in California, etc).
So:
1. Winston Churchill is British
2. All British people smoke cigars
3. Therefore, Winston Churchill smokes cigars
Becomes:
1. w is B
2. All B is C
3. Therefore, w is C
Star all distributed terms in the premises, and all undistributed terms in the conclusion:
1. w is B
2. All B* is C
3. Therefore, w* is C*
Then imagine two columns, with the letters going down. There should be just one term starred in the right hand "column", and each capital letter should be starred once and only once.
B and C are both starred once (don't worry about lowercase letters), and in the right hand column there is just one starred letter (the C).
So the argument is logically valid.
Pretty neat, huh?
I'm currently working my way through Gensler's logic book. It's quite good. Although the quantificational logic chapter is hurting my brain a bit.
Which of Gensler's books are you using? Intro to Logic? He has several that look interesting.
Yep. Intro to Logic. You can also do a google search for logicola, his program that lets you solve logic problems, from syllogisms through modal logic and on up. It goes with the book.
OK. I just ordered a used one from the Amazon associates. Don't know when it will be here. A fellow can't have too many logic books.
After you get it, don't forget to download and install this.
So much easier to use a program to do these practice exercises.
Post a Comment